1. Po raz pierwszy odwiedzasz EDU. LEARN

    Odwiedzasz EDU.LEARN

    Najlepszym sposobem na naukę języka jest jego używanie. W EDU.LEARN znajdziesz interesujące teksty i videa, które dadzą Ci taką właśnie możliwość. Nie przejmuj się - nasze filmiki mają napisy, dzięki którym lepiej je zrozumiesz. Dodatkowo, po kliknięciu na każde słówko, otrzymasz jego tłumaczenie oraz prawidłową wymowę.

    Nie, dziękuję
  2. Mini lekcje

    Podczas nauki języka bardzo ważny jest kontekst. Zdjęcia, przykłady użycia, dialogi, nagrania dźwiękowe - wszystko to pomaga Ci zrozumieć i zapamiętać nowe słowa i wyrażenia. Dlatego stworzyliśmy Mini lekcje. Są to krótkie lekcje, zawierające kontekstowe slajdy, które zwiększą efektywność Twojej nauki. Są cztery typy Mini lekcji - Gramatyka, Dialogi, Słówka i Obrazki.

    Dalej
  3. Wideo

    Ćwicz język obcy oglądając ciekawe filmiki. Wybierz temat, który Cię interesuje oraz poziom trudności, a następnie kliknij na filmik. Nie martw się, obok każdego z nich są napisy. A może wcale nie będą Ci one potrzebne? Spróbuj!

    Dalej
  4. Teksty

    Czytaj ciekawe artykuły, z których nauczysz się nowych słówek i dowiesz więcej o rzeczach, które Cię interesują. Podobnie jak z filmikami, możesz wybrać temat oraz poziom trudności, a następnie kliknąć na wybrany artykuł. Nasz interaktywny słownik pomoże Ci zrozumieć nawet trudne teksty, a kontekst ułatwi zapamiętanie słówek. Dodatkowo, każdy artykuł może być przeczytany na głos przez wirtualnego lektora, dzięki czemu ćwiczysz słuchanie i wymowę!

    Dalej
  5. Słowa

    Tutaj możesz znaleźć swoją listę "Moje słówka", czyli funkcję wyszukiwania słówek - a wkrótce także słownik tematyczny. Do listy "Moje słówka" możesz dodawać słowa z sekcji Videa i Teksty. Każde z słówek dodanych do listy możesz powtórzyć później w jednym z naszych ćwiczeń. Dodatkowo, zawsze możesz iść do swojej listy i sprawdzić znaczenie, wymowę oraz użycie słówka w zdaniu. Użyj naszej wyszukiwarki słówek w części "Słownictwo", aby znaleźć słowa w naszej bazie.

    Dalej
  6. Lista tekstów

    Ta lista tekstów pojawia się po kliknięciu na "Teksty". Wybierz poziom trudności oraz temat, a następnie artykuł, który Cię interesuje. Kiedy już zostaniesz do niego przekierowany, kliknij na "Play", jeśli chcesz, aby został on odczytany przez wirtualnego lektora. W ten sposób ćwiczysz umiejętność słuchania. Niektóre z tekstów są szczególnie interesujące - mają one odznakę w prawym górnym rogu. Koniecznie je przeczytaj!

    Dalej
  7. Lista Video

    Ta lista filmików pojawia się po kliknięciu na "Video". Podobnie jak w przypadku Tekstów, najpierw wybierz temat, który Cię interesuje oraz poziom trudności, a następnie kliknij na wybrane video. Te z odznaką w prawym górnym rogu są szczególnie interesujące - nie przegap ich!

    Dalej
  8. Dziękujemy za skorzystanie z przewodnika!

    Teraz już znasz wszystkie funkcje EDU.LEARN! Przygotowaliśmy do Ciebie wiele artykułów, filmików oraz mini lekcji - na pewno znajdziesz coś, co Cię zainteresuje!

    Teraz zapraszamy Cię do zarejestrowania się i odkrycia wszystkich możliwości portalu.

    Dziękuję, wrócę później
  9. Lista Pomocy

    Potrzebujesz z czymś pomocy? Sprawdź naszą listę poniżej:
    Nie, dziękuję

Już 62 425 użytkowników uczy się języków obcych z Edustation.

Możesz zarejestrować się już dziś i odebrać bonus w postaci 10 monet.

Jeżeli chcesz się dowiedzieć więcej o naszym portalu - kliknij tutaj

Jeszcze nie teraz

lub

Poziom:

Wszystkie

Nie masz konta?

2. Death with Shelly Kagan: The nature of persons: dualism vs. physicalism


Poziom:

Temat: Edukacja

Professor Shelly Kagan: The first question we want to
discuss has to do with the possibility of my surviving my
death. Is there life after death?
Is there a possibility that I might still exist or survive
after my death? Now at first glance--and in
fact, I think, at second glance it's going to
turn out to be true--you might think that the answer to this
question would depend on two basic issues.
Do I survive my death? Do we survive our deaths?
You think, the first thing we have to get clear on is well
what am I? What kind of a thing am I?
Or generalizing, what kind of thing is a person?
What are we made of? What are our parts?
It seems plausible to think that before we could answer the
question, "Do I survive?" we need to know how I'm built.
And so the first thing we're going to spend a fair bit of
time on is trying to get clear on what's a person?
What are the fundamental building blocks of a person?
The second question that you might think we'd want to get
clear on is, "What's the idea, or what's the concept,
of surviving?" Before we ask, "Do I survive?"
we need to get clear on "What am I?"
and "What is it to survive?" What is it for something that
exists in the future to be me? Now this question can be
discussed philosophically in quite general terms.
What's the nature of persistence of identity over
time? But since we're especially
interested in beings like us, people, this topic,
this sub-specialized version of the question of identity,
gets discussed under the rubric of the topic,
personal identity. What's the key or the nature or
the basis of personal identity? As we might put it:
What is it for somebody who's here next week to be the same
person as me? What's the nature of personal
identity? So, as I say,
at first glance you might think to get clear on the answer,
"Do I or might I or could I survive my death?"
we need to know, what am I? What's a person?
What's the metaphysical composition of people,
on the one hand? And we need to get clear on the
nature of identity or persistence or,
more specifically, personal identity.
Now as I say, I believe that when push comes
to shove, we do need to get clear about both of those
questions and so that's going to take the first several weeks of
the class. We're going to spend a couple
of weeks talking about, "What's a person?"
And then we're going to spend several weeks,
or at least a week or so, talking about the nature of
personal identity. But before we can even get
started, there's a question, really an objection to the
whole enterprise. So we're about to spend a lot
of time asking the philosophical question: Is there life after
death? Could there be life after death?
Might I survive my death? But there's a philosophical
objection to the entire question.
And the objection is fairly simple.
It says the whole question is misconceived.
It's based on a confusion. Once we see the confusion,
we can see what the answer to our question is.
Could I survive my death? The answer has got to be--this
is what the objection says--the answer has got to be,
obviously not. All right, so here's the
objection. I should mention that the very
first reading that you're going to be doing is a couple of pages
from Jay Rosenberg, a contemporary philosopher.
He gives us a version of this objection.
So I'll give you one version. You'll have another version in
your readings. The objection basically says:
What does it mean to say that somebody's died?
We're asking, "Is there life after death?"
What does it mean to say that somebody has died?
Well a natural definition of death might be something like
the end of life. So then, if that's right,
then to ask, "Is there life after death?"
is just asking, "Is there life after the end of
life?" The answer to that ought to be
pretty obvious. Well, obviously,
the answer to that is no. After all, if we're saying once
you've run out of life, is there any more life?
Well, duh! That's like asking,
when I've eaten up all the food on my plate, is there any food
left on my plate? Or what happens in the movie
after the movie ends? These are stupid questions,
because once you understand what they're asking,
the answer is just built in. It follows trivially.
So although it has seemed to people over the ages that the
question, "Is there life after death?"
is one of the great mysteries, one of the great philosophical
things to ponder, the objection says that's a
kind of illusion. In fact, once you think about
it, and not all that long, you can see the answer's got to
be no. There couldn't possibly be life
after death. There couldn't possibly be life
after the end of life. Or suppose we ask the question
in a slightly different way. Might I survive my death?
Well what does the word "survive" mean?
Well, survive is something like we say that somebody's a
survivor if something's happened and they haven't died.
They're still alive. When there's a car accident,
you ask, so-and-so died, so-and-so survived.
This person survived. To say that they survived is
just saying that they're still alive.
So, "Might I survive my death?" is like asking,
"Might I still be alive after"--well what's death?
Death is the end of life. So-- "might I still be alive
after I've stopped living? Might I be one of the people
who didn't die when I died?" Gosh, the answer to that is,
again, duh! No.
You couldn't possibly survive your death, given the very
definition. It should remind us of--at
least it reminds me of this joke that you probably told.
It seemed hysterical when you were seven.
The plane crashes exactly on the border of Canada and the
United States. Exactly on the border.
There's dead people everywhere. Where do they bury the
survivors? The answer is:
You don't bury the survivors. So when you're seven you think,
"I don't know. Do they bury them in Canada?
Do they bury them in America?" The answer is:
You don't bury the survivors, because survivors are people
that haven't yet died. So, "Can I survive my death?"
is like asking, "Could I not have yet died
after…?" The answer is,
of course, you have to have died if you died and you haven't
survived if you've died. So the question can't even get
off the ground. That, at least,
is how the objection goes. Now I don't mean to be utterly
dismissive of the objection. That's why I spent a couple of
minutes trying to spell it out. But I think there's a way to
respond to it. We just have to get clearer
about what precisely the question is that we're trying to
ask. This is something that
Rosenberg tries to get clear on as well.
So here's my attempt to make the question both a bit more
precise, and a question that's an open question.
A question we can legitimately raise.
Well, now as you will hear on several occasions over the
course of the semester, I'm a philosopher.
What that means is I don't really know a whole lot of
facts. So I'm about to tell you a
story where I wish I knew the facts.
I don't know the facts. If I could really do it right,
I'd now open the door and bring in our guest physiologist,
who would then provide the facts that I'm--what I'm about
to go is "blah, blah, blah."
But we have the physiologist come in and he'd actually tell
us these things. I don't know them.
I don't have that person. But take a look at what happens
when a body dies. Now, no doubt,
you can kill people in a lot of different ways.
You can poison them, you can strangle them,
you can shoot them in the heart.
The causal paths that result in death may start different,
but I presume that they converge and you end up having a
set of events take place. Now what are those events?
This is exactly where I don't really know the details,
but I take it it's something like: because of whatever the
original input was, eventually the blood's no
longer circulating and oxygen isn't making its way around the
body. So the brain becomes
oxygen-starved. Because of the lack of oxygen
getting to the cells, the cells are no longer able to
carry on their various metabolic processes.
Because of this, they can't repair the various
kinds of damage they need, or create the amino acids and
proteins they need. So as decay begins to set in
and the cell structures begin to break down, they don't get
repaired as they would normally do,
and so eventually have breakdown of the crucial cell
structure and boom, the body's dead.
Now as I say, I don't really know whether
that's accurate, the little rough story I just
told, but some story like that is probably right.
And in typical philosophical fashion, I've drawn that story
for you up here on the board. So the events that I don't
really know the details of, we can just call B_1,
B_2, B_3,
up through B_n. Before B_1 begins,
you've got the body working, functioning,
in its bodily way--respirating, reproducing the cells,
and so forth and so on. And at the end of the process,
by B_n, the body's dead.
B for bodily. B_1 through
B_n; that's what death is.
At least, that's what death of the body is.
As I say, it's the sort of thing that somebody from the
medical school or a biologist or a physiologist or something
could describe for us. So here's the question then.
Suppose we call that process "death of the body."
Call what has occurred by the end of that sequence of events,
"bodily death." Now here's a question that we
can still ask, at least it looks as though we
can still ask it. Might I, or do I,
still exist after the death of my body?
Might I still exist after bodily death?
I don't mean to suggest in any way that we yet know the answer
to that question, but at least that's a question
that it seems as though we can coherently raise.
There's no obvious contradiction in asking:
Might I still exist after the death of my body?
The answer could turn out to be no.
But at least it's not obviously no.
If the answer turns out to be no, it's going to take some
sustained argument to settle it one way or the other.
The answer could turn out to be yes, for all we know at this
point. This just brings us back to the
thought that whether or not I could still exist after the
death of my body looks like it should depend on what I am.
So in a minute, that's the question that I'm
going to turn to. But it's a bit cumbersome to
constantly be asking: Might I still exist after the
death of my body? So no harm is done,
once we've clarified the question that we're trying to
ask, if we summarize that question in a bit of a jargon or
slogan. We say, instead of asking:
Might I survive? Or: Might I continue to exist
after the death of my body? --you might put it this way.
You might say for short: Will I survive the death of my
body? No harm done.
Or: Will I survive my death? Because what we were just
stipulating we mean when we talk about my death in the context of
this question is the death of my body.
No harm done. We can just say for short:
Will I survive my death or might I survive my death?
For that matter, no serious harm done if we ask:
Is there life after death? As long as we understand that
what we're not asking about there is life of my body.
Just another familiar way of trying to ask:
Will I still be around after my death?
Will I still exist after my death?
So I think there's a perfectly legitimate question and that's
the question we now want to turn to.
As I said, it looks as though to answer the question,
"Could I continue to exist after the death of my
body?"--"Is there life after death?"
"Could I survive my death?" for short--to answer that
question, we need to get clearer about: What exactly is it for
something to be me? That's a question we'll turn to
in a couple of weeks. First, we've got to get clearer
about: What am I? What kind of an entity am I?
What am I made of? In philosophical jargon,
this is a question from metaphysics.
So we're asking the metaphysical question:
What kind of a thing is a person?
It seems plausible to think that whether or not a person can
survive or continue to exist after the death of his or her
body should depend on how he's built,
what he's made of, what his or her parts are.
So, let me sketch for you two basic positions on this
question. What is a person?
Two basic positions. They're both,
I imagine, fairly familiar. What we're going to have to do
is try to decide between them. They're not the only possible
positions on the question of the metaphysics of the person.
But they're, I think, the two most prominent
positions and definitely the ones most worth taking seriously
for our purposes. So, first possible position is
this. A person is a combination of a
body and something else--a mind. But the crucial thing about
this first view that we want to talk about is that the mind is
thought of as something separate from,
and distinct from, the body. To use a common enough word,
it's a soul. So people are,
or people have, or people consist of,
bodies and souls. The soul is something,
as I say, distinct from the body.
I take it the idea of the body is a familiar one.
It's this lump of flesh and bone and muscle that's sitting
here in front of you and that each one of you sort of drags
around with you. It's the sort of thing that we
can put on a scale and prod with a stick and the biologists can
study, presumably made up of various
kinds of molecules, atoms and so forth.
So we've got the body. But on this first view,
we also have something that's not body.
Something that's not a material object.
Something that's not composed of molecules and atoms.
It's a soul. It's the house of,
or the seat of, or the basis of,
consciousness and thinking, perhaps personality.
But the crucial point for this view is that the proper
metaphysical understanding of the mind is to think of it in
nonphysical terms, nonmaterial terms.
That, as I say, is the first basic view.
I'm going to say more about that view, a fair bit more about
that view, over the next couple of weeks.
First, let me sketch the other basic view.
So this first view we can call "the dualist view."
Dualist, of course, because there's two basic
components--the body and the soul.
Although I may occasionally slip, I'm going to try to
preserve the word "soul." When I use the word "soul," I'm
going to have in mind this dualist view according to which
the soul is something immaterial, nonphysical.
Some other kind--the body is a material substance.
The soul is an immaterial substance.
That's the dualist view. The alternative view that we're
going to consider is not dualist, but monist.
It says there's one basic kind of thing and only one basic kind
of thing. There are bodies.
So what's a person? A person is just a certain kind
of material object. A person is just a body.
Of course, it's a very fancy material object.
It's a very amazing material object.
That's what this second view says.
The person is a body that can do things that most other
material objects can't do. So on the monist view--which
we'll call "physicalism," because it says that what people
just are, are these physical objects--on
the physicalist view, a person is just a body that
can…now you fill in the blank. You point out the kinds of
things that we can do. We can talk.
We can think. We can sing.
We can write poetry. We can fall in love.
We can be afraid. We can make plans.
We can discover things about the universe.
According to the physicalist view, a person is just a body
that can do all of those things: can reflect,
can be rational, can communicate,
can make plans, can fall in love,
can write poetry. That's the physicalist view.
As I say, we've got two basic positions.
There's the dualist view--people are bodies and
souls. And there's the physicalist
view, according to which there are no souls.
There are no immaterial objects like that.
There are only bodies, though when you've got a
functioning body like ours, so the physicalist says,
these bodies can do some pretty amazing things.
The kind of things that we all know people can do.
Two basic views. From a logical point of view,
I suppose you might have a third possible view.
If we've got the monist who says there's bodies but there's
no souls, you could imagine somebody who says there are
souls but there are no bodies. This would roughly be a view
according to which there are minds, but there aren't really
physical objects. Physical objects are a kind of
illusion, perhaps, that we fall into.
Or thinking about them in materialistic terms might be
greatly confused or mistaken. This view is sometimes known in
philosophy as idealism: all that exists,
are minds and their ideas. Physical objects is just a way
of talking about the ideas the mind has or something like that.
Idealism is a position that's got a very long history in
philosophy and for many classes would be worth taking a fair bit
of time to consider more carefully.
But for our purposes, I think it's not a contender.
So I'm just going to put it aside.
The positions that I'm going to--and there are other
possibilities as well. There are views where mind and
body are just two different ways of looking at the same
underlying reality where the underlying reality is neither
physical nor mental. That view's also worth taking
seriously in a metaphysics class, but for our purposes,
I mention it and put it aside. The two views we are going to
focus on are, on the one hand,
the dualist view--people have souls as well as bodies--and the
physicalist view--all we have, all we are, are bodies.
Let me say something more then about the dualist position.
According to the dualist, the mind is this immaterial
substance and we could call it by different names.
No harm would be done if we call it a mind,
though the reason I will typically talk about a soul is
to try to flag the crucial point of the dualist view.
The mind is based in, or just is something
nonphysical, something nonmaterial…The soul can
direct and give orders to the body, on the one hand.
On the other hand, the body generates input that
eventually gets sensed or felt by the soul.
You take a pin and you stick it through my flesh of my body and
I feel pain in my soul, in my mind.
So, two-way interaction. As always with philosophy,
there's more complicated versions of dualism where maybe
the interaction doesn't work both ways,
but let's just limit ourselves to good, old-fashioned,
two-way interactionist dualism. So my mind controls my body.
My body can affect my mind in various ways.
But for all that, they're separate things.
Still there's this very tight connection.
We sometimes put it: the soul is in the body,
though talking about spatial locations here may be somewhat
metaphorically intended. It's not as though we think
that if you start opening up the body you'd finally find the
particular spot. Here's the place where the soul
is located. Though it does seem,
from this dualist perspective, as though souls are located,
I'm sort of viewing the world from here.
Just like each of you is viewing the world from a
particular location. So maybe your soul is located,
more or less, in the vicinity of your body.
Crucial point, of course, the attraction of
the dualist view, from our point of view,
is that if there's a soul as well as the body,
and the soul is something immaterial,
then when the body dies, when we have B_1
through B_n and the death of the body occurs.
So at the end of B_n, the body stops repairing
itself. Decay sets in.
We all know the sad story. The worms crawl in,
the worms crawl out. At the end of the day--well it
maybe it takes longer than a day--the body has decomposed.
Yes, all that bespeaks the end of the body.
But if the soul is something immaterial, then that could
continue to exist, even after the destruction of
the body. That's the attraction,
at least one of the attractions, of the dualist
view. The belief in the soul gives
you something to continue to exist after the end of your
body. So what's death?
Well, if normally there's this super tight connection between
my soul and my body, death might be the severing of
that connection. So the body breaks and no
longer is able to give input up to the soul.
The soul is no longer able to control the body and make it
move around. But for all that,
the soul might continue to exist.
And so at least the possibility that I'll survive my death is
one worth taking very, very seriously if we are
dualists.
A couple of things to point out about this view.
One is I've been talking as though a person is a
combination, kind of a soul and body sandwich.
So a person has two basic building blocks.
The bodily part and the soul part.
It's natural to talk that way, but if we want belief in the
soul to help us hold out the possibility at least that there
might be life after death, then I think we need to
actually say that strictly speaking, it's not that a person
is a soul plus a body. Strictly speaking,
I think we need to say the person just is the soul.
After all, if the person is the combination, if the person is
the pair, soul plus the body, destroy the body,
you've destroyed the pair. If the person is the pair and
the pair no longer exists, the person no longer exists.
So if we want belief in a soul to help us leave open the door
to the possibility that I survive the destruction of my
body, it had better not be that the
body is an essential part of me. It's simpler,
more straightforward to say instead, "What I am strictly
speaking is a soul." As long as the soul exists,
I exist.
Of course, my soul, me, I, have a very tight
connection to a particular body. But still, you could,
in principle, destroy the body without
destroying me. Look, I have a particularly
close connection to the house I live in.
But for all that, you can destroy my house
without destroying me. So that's I think the position
that we ought to ascribe to the dualist.
The person is, strictly speaking,
the soul. The soul has a very intimate
connection with the body, but the person is not the soul
and the body. The person is just the soul.
So even if that intimate connection gets destroyed,
the person, the soul, could continue to exist.
The second point to clear up is that there's really three
different issues that might interest us.
One, metaphysically, are bodies and souls distinct?
Is the mind to be understood in terms of this immaterial object,
the soul? So are there two kinds of
things? That's the first question.
Are souls and bodies distinct? Second question,
though, is: Does the soul, even if it exists,
survive the destruction of the body?
It could be something separate without surviving.
That's why I've tried to say if there are souls,
at least that opens the door to the possibility that we will
survive our death. But, it doesn't guarantee it,
because absent further argumentation,
there's no guarantee that the soul survives the death of the
body. Even if it's separate,
it could be that it gets killed at the very same time or
destroyed at the very same time that the body's being destroyed.
Maybe when these physical processes, B_1 through
B_n, take place,
they set into motion--remember, after all we're interactionist
dualists. There's this very tight causal
connection between the body and the mind and the soul and the
body, the body and the soul. Just like when you prick my
body, that bodily process sets up certain things taking place
in my soul. Maybe when B_1
through B_n take place, they set up some other
processes in my soul. Call them S_1 through
S_n. And maybe S_1 through
S_n results in the destruction of my soul.
So simultaneously with my body dying, my soul dies.
Okay, this one's going to be a little bit trickier to draw.
The first part, S_1...,
that's easy. S_n.
The question is: How do I draw the soul?
I don't really know .
So the mere fact that we decide, if we do ultimately
decide that there is a soul, something nonphysical,
separate and distinct from the body, doesn't guarantee that we
survive our physical death. That's going to be a separate
question we'll have to turn to. The first question's going to
be: Are there any souls? Next question is going to have
to be: If there are, do we have any good reason to
think that they survive the death of the body?
Third question that might interest us, that does interest
us, is this: If it survives, how long does it survive?
Does the soul continue to exist after the death of the body?
Does it continue to exist forever?
Are we immortal?
Most of us would like that to be true.
We want there to be souls so that we can be immortal.
And so the question's got to be not only, is the soul distinct?
Does it survive the death of my body?
But does it continue to exist forever?
Those questions--hang on one second--are ones that especially
interest Plato. So in about a week or so we'll
start reading Plato's Phaedo.
The purpose of that dialogue, of that philosophical work,
is to argue for the immortality of the soul.
That's a question we'll be turning to.
Yeah? Student: [inaudible]
Professor Shelly Kagan: Great.
So the question is this. If the very idea of soul that
we're working with here under the dualist picture is the soul
as an immaterial substance, it's not made of ordinary
atomic matter. If the soul is immaterial,
doesn't it follow automatically,
trivially, that the soul can't be destroyed by a material
process? After all, there was death of
the body, B_1 through B_n.
That's a material process, a physical process.
Doesn't it follow that a soul, an immaterial entity,
can't be destroyed by a material, physical process?
That's a great question. What I want to say is,
the short answer for now is, I don't think it follows
automatically. It doesn't follow trivially.
It may follow. Plato's actually going to give
us some arguments for pretty much that same claim.
Plato's going to argue once we understand the sort of
metaphysical nature of the soul, we'll see why it couldn't be
destroyed. That's going to take some fancy
arguments. The reason I think it doesn't
follow trivially is because, remember, I said we're dealing
with interactionist dualism. We've already admitted that
bodies are able to affect the soul, right?
The body is having all sorts of light bounce off my eyes of
various wavelengths. And because of that my soul is
having various visual sensations about the number of people in
front of me, colors, and so forth and so on.
I gave the example of pricking my body.
That's a physical process that causes some sorts of changes in
the mental processes occurring in my soul.
Once we've admitted that on this kind of dualist picture the
material body can influence what happens in the immaterial soul,
then it doesn't seem that we have any grounds for shutting
the door to the possibility that the right physical process,
B_1 through B_n,
might set up this horrible mental, soul process,
S_1 through S_n,
resulting in the destruction of the soul.
It's a possibility. It's going to take more
arguments to rule it out. Yeah?
Student: [inaudible] Professor Shelly Kagan:
Yeah, another great question. The question was:
I said it seems plausible to say my soul is located,
more or less, here because I seem to view the
world from here. But maybe that's not right.
Maybe we shouldn't talk about the location of the soul at all.
After all, if the soul is an immaterial object,
can immaterial objects have locations?
I don't know. The short answer is I don't
know. I know very little about how
immaterial objects are supposed to work.
So although I'm trying to sketch the dualist position,
as I explained on Tuesday, I don't myself believe in
souls. I don't actually think that the
dualist view is correct. You might say,
I'll leave that problem--are souls spatially located or
not--to be worked out by those who believe in it.
For our purposes, I think it doesn't really
matter. If you want to say souls have a
location, where are they located?
They're located more or less where my body is.
At least, as long as my body's working.
Maybe at death the soul gets liberated from the body and is
able to wander more freely. Sometimes people talk about,
in fact we'll be reading about this, out-of-body experiences.
And so maybe during those unusual times the soul wanders
from the body and comes back to it.
Or, alternatively, maybe the soul doesn't have any
location at all. Maybe that's just an illusion
created by the fact that I'm getting this visual input from
my body. My body certainly has a
location. Maybe the right way--imagine
somebody who was in a room with remote control television setup
and so forth and so on. And he's seeing what's
happening in Chicago, even though he's sitting in a
room in New Haven. Well, you could understand why
he might fall into the trap of thinking of himself as located
in Chicago with all the visual inputs coming from Chicago.
So maybe that's how it works with the soul.
We get lulled into thinking that we are where our bodies
are. But that's really a
metaphysical illusion. I don't really know.
For our purposes, I think it's not crucial.
Though it's a great question, but I'm not going to try to
pursue it any further. All right.
So one question: Is there a soul?
Second question: Does it survive the death of
our body? Third question:
If it does, does it live forever?
Does it continue to exist forever?
Is the soul immortal? We will initially think about
the first question: Do we have any good reason to
believe in souls at all? And only after a while will we
turn to the second and third question: Does it survive and,
more particularly, is it immortal?
That's the first basic view about the nature of a person.
A person has a soul, something immaterial and not a
body. I take it that the view is a
familiar one. Many of you probably believe in
it. Those of you who don't believe
in it have probably, at least, been tempted to
believe in it. I'm sure you all do know people
who believe in it. It's a very familiar picture.
But, of course, the question we're going to
have to ask ourselves is: Is it right?
Is there reasons to believe it's correct?
Turn now to the second basic view, the physicalist view,
according to which a person is just a body.
This is a materialist view. People are just material
objects, the sorts of things biologists poke and prod and
study. It's important--I think this is
the crucial point--that when we say a person is just a body,
we don't understand that to mean--the physicalist doesn't
mean that as--a person is just any old body.
It's not as though there aren't important differences between
different physical objects. Some physical objects can do
things of a far more interesting sort than other physical
objects. Here's a piece of chalk.
It's a physical object. It's just a body.
What can it do? Well, not a whole lot.
I can write on the board with it.
I can break it in two. You let go of it, it drops down.
Not a very interesting physical body.
Here's a cell phone. It's just a body.
It's not the most interesting physical object in the world,
but it's a whole lot more interesting than a piece of
chalk. It can do all sorts of things a
piece of chalk can't do. If the physicalist is right,
then here's another physical object for you--me,
Shelly Kagan. I'm a pretty impressive
physical object. Now arrogant as I may be,
I don't mean to suggest I'm any more impressive than you guys
are. Each one of us,
according to the physicalist, is just a body that can do some
amazing things. We are bodies that can think.
We are bodies that can plan. We are bodies that can reason.
We are bodies that can feel. We are bodies that can be
afraid and be creative and have dreams and aspirations.
We are bodies that can communicate with each other.
We are bodies that are--well, here's a word for it:
We're bodies that are people. But on the physicalist view,
a person is just a body. And that's where we'll take it
up next time.
Mobile Analytics